Skip to main content
SearchLoginLogin or Signup

The Porous Mask. A Theological Reflection on Concepts of Personhood and Personal Agency in the Digital Age

Published onNov 06, 2019
The Porous Mask. A Theological Reflection on Concepts of Personhood and Personal Agency in the Digital Age
·
Dr. Florian Hoehne | Theologies of the Digital

Introduction1

In his description of a possibly emerging »Dataism«, Yuval Harari writes about humans as »data-processing systems«.2 This is remarkable for at least the following reason: The philosopher Martin Buber prominently distinguished between things and personal agents, between the »realm of it« and the »realm of thou«.3 Calling humans »data processing systems« treats them as things, not as persons. Digital transformations have raised many questions around artificial intelligence, autonomous computer systems and singularity, questions of whether, where and how it might make practical or theoretical sense to treat computer systems as persons. A deeper question resonates in all these debates: Does it make sense to treat human beings as persons? The maybe surprising answer of Harari’s »data religion« would be that it does not make sense; Instead, human beings would function as »data processing systems«. In this paper, I want to point to a notion of personhood that makes it possible to object to dataism’s answer.

Some narratives by which people make sense of digital transformations speak about human persons in computer-metaphors. Harari’s »data religion« is one example for that. The following sentences, written by Douglas Rushkoff, are another example: »In the emerging, highly programmed landscape ahead, you will either create the software or you will be the software. It’s really that simple: Program, or be programmed.«4 Seeing humans as »software« and as potentially programmable or even »programmed« puts personhood in question on a metaphorical level—and it is obviously plausible to do so under conditions of digital communication. Not only the machine’s personhood but human personhood is on the line.5 This raises philosophical, ethical, and practical questions: What does it mean to treat another human being and oneself as persons and not only as things, systems, or software? What follows from treating each other as persons, and what makes an entity prone to being treated as a person? What is the ethical value of treating each other as persons and not just as systems or software? How do digital transformations alter our understanding of personhood and of each other as persons? Given that the Greek origin of the term »person« also refers to the mask of the actor,6 which features of the mask that is »personhood« make it possible to give it to people? Which features become more or less plausible under condition of digital communication? What practical differences do these features make?

While the philosophical and theological literature on these issues fills libraries,7 I am quite selectively interested in how we can imagine each other and ourselves as persons under conditions of digital communication in a way that maintains and establishes human agency, particularly of those not in power to program. I am interested in a sense of personhood that lies between the two poles of Rushkoff’s digital alternative of either actively programming or passively programmed selves. The thesis of this paper is based on the distinction of two ways of imagining personal agency—two types of masks, so to say—inspired by Bernhard Waldenfels:8 forensic imaginations and responsorial imaginations of personal agency. My thesis is that the power dynamics in a digital age undermine forensic imaginations and the possibility of personal agency. However, the practical promotion of responsorial imaginations would counter this development. The aim of my argument is not to adapt the ethical notion of personhood to digital transformations but rather to suggest a notion of personhood that sustains human agency in a digital world.

In order to make this point, I will first explain the socio-philosophical categories I work with (1), then describe the forensic imagination of personal agency in its practical ambivalence (2), show how digital power dynamics alter these imaginations (3), and interpret Bonhoeffer’s Ethics in terms of a responsorial imagination of personal agency (4). I will finish by pointing to the practical difference this makes (5).

1: Categories: Praxis and Imagination

Particularly two categories situate the following reflections and their consequences in their social context: The category of practice as used in sociological theories of praxis after the so called »practice turn«9 and the category of imagination as used by Charles Taylor in his writings on modern social imaginaries.10 The idea to talk about digital ethics in terms of imaginations, narratives, and social practices has been developed at the Berlin Institute for Public Theology and is explained at greater length in other publications.11 For this paper, the following points are important:

Following Theodore Schatzki and Andreas Reckwitz, I understand a practice as a »nexus of doings and sayings« bound together by routine or implicit knowledge.12 As such, practices are always socially and contextually situated13 and involve things, bodies, and some kind of practical knowledge.14 For example, the practice of turning on the light in a smart home involves something like the following: a speech act that commands the computer-system to turn on the lights, the action to step into the dark room, the routinized implicit knowledge of how to talk with the computer as well as the body that speaks and acts, and the things the body has to do with—in this case: the computer, the room, the lights.

One thought from theories of social practice is particularly important here because it shifts the focus from digital technologies to cultures of digital technology use. Andreas Reckwitz has emphasized that the relation of things and actual practices is not one-sided15: Things do not totally determine a practice nor do practices totally determine things. Rather, the »meaningful use«16 of certain things that is inseparable from the actual practice is decisive. To use an example:17 The invention of the printing press has not necessitated its historic career. Rather, the spread of printing machines and printing books is due to the rise of socially situated and contextual practices that make meaningful use of printing machines and printed books—namely, the culturally evolving practices of reading and publication. Simultaneously, those practices are made possible by the existence of printing machines. Hence, there is a sociological reason to not only reflect the technology and its potential, but more importantly to reflect how people use and make sense of technology culturally.

This makes the second category—the social imaginary—crucial for a theological reflection of digital cultural practices. According to Charles Taylor, people draw on a common social imaginary whenever they act, make sense of their social existence, or participate in social practices. He writes:

»By social imaginary, I mean something much broader and deeper than the intellectual schemes people may entertain when they think about social reality in a disengaged mode. I am thinking, rather, of the ways people imagine their social existence, how they fit together with others, how things go on between them and their fellows, the expectations that are normally met, and the deeper normative notions and images that underlie these expectations.«18

According to Taylor, the social imaginary is the background for any immediate practical knowledge that makes concrete practices possible.19 In other words: it provides the horizon for meaningful practices.20 It refers to the imaginations of the participants of social practices rather than to a theoretical perspective on social realities; the imagined is »carried in images, stories and legends«.21

How then can we envision the relation between the imaginary and concrete practices? Following Taylor and exceeding Taylor’s thinking just a little in terms of a theory of social practices, I suggest thinking of this relation as mutual: On the one hand, the social imaginary makes social practices possible and informs them.22 That we imagine others and ourselves as primarily free individuals23 informs practices of intimate relationships as well as of administration. Simultaneously, the social imaginary persists and exists in the very practices it informs. The transformation of practices also transforms the social imaginary in whose horizon people make sense of those transformations and meaningfully participate in them.

Presupposing this interrelation of imaginations and practices, I will ask how the imaginary of personal agency persists and changes in the practices of digital communication it simultaneously informs. My starting point for this is one image from the modern social imaginary that is in continuity with modern and premodern Christian imaginations: namely, the forensic imagination of the person people hold on to when they treat each other as persons. I will use the word »imagination« to refer to individual imaginations taken from the social imaginary.

2: Imaginaries I: The Forensic Imagination of Personhood (John Locke)

What I will call the »forensic imagination of personal agency« is not decisive for all concepts of the person. Rather, it plays an important role in the western modern social imaginary24: We imagine ourselves and others as accountable for and conscious of our actions and their consequences over time—and that is precisely one imagination which the word »person« refers to. By treating each other as persons, we are treating each other as accountable over time. Practically, »person« denotes an entity to which one can attribute past actions and consequences, in order to hold that person accountable, to ask for a justification, or to punish and reward.25 This image is forensic, insofar as it entails the image of a court-situation, be it an actual human court, the Last Judgment, or the conscience as inner court.

The relation between actor and action might sound either self-evident or ontologically given. If it sounds self-evident, this gives proof to this imagination being part of the western modern social imaginary. Yet it is still a contextual and socially situated imagination. One indication for this is that such an imagination is not equally plausible for all positions in a society. Having experienced oneself as a powerful actor whose actions make a difference in social life will make the forensic imagination of accountable agency for an individual seem more plausible. It is less plausible for those who experience themselves always and only as the object of external decision-making processes. If the relation between actor and action sounds ontologically given, a discussion of ontology is opened, which is unnecessary here, for one simple reason: What becomes socially relevant in the aftermath of an action is the social imaginary independent of the ontological reality it refers to. To put it in an example: By having even accused a person of causing harm, the social imagination of personal accountability is presupposed—independent of whether a given person actually caused a certain harmful consequence.

Historically, the forensic image of personal agency is already manifest in John Locke’s famous concept of personhood.26 Since Charles Taylor also refers to Locke to describe the modern social imaginary, his writings on personhood might be a good exemplification of the forensic type, even though Taylor does not refer to this part.27 Locke is famous for having pinned the notion of being a person to consciousness, thereby making personal identity independent of the identity of matter and substance.28 Locke writes, that the term »person« refers to

»a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places; which it does only by that consciousness which is inseparable from thinking, and as it seems to me essential to it […]; in this alone consists personal identity, i.e., the sameness of a rational being: and as far as this consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person«.29

Thereby, Locke identifies being a person with the actual proceeding of—and not only the potentiality for—self-reflective consciousness internal to the entity. Being a person means to be self-conscious of one’s past and present actions. To put it in the aforementioned metaphor: it is the self-consciousness, the consciousness of one’s actions behind the mask that makes the mask a persona, that makes the person perform as a person.

In the end of his chapter on »Identity and Diversity« (which Locke added in the second edition of his Essay30), Locke makes explicit that this is meant as a forensic notion of personhood. He also makes clear why and how consciousness is so decisive. He writes:

»Person, as I take it, is the name for this self. […] It is a forensic term appropriating actions and their merit; and so belongs only to intelligent agents capable of a law, and happiness and misery. This personality extends itself beyond present existence to what is past, only by consciousness; whereby it becomes concerned and accountable, owns and imputes to itself past actions, just upon the same ground and for the same reason that it does the present. All which is founded in a concern for happiness, the unavoidable concomitant of consciousness; that which is conscious of pleasure and pain desiring that that self that is conscious should be happy.«31

Hence, the term »person« names an entity that—by virtue of its consciousness—can be held accountable, punished and rewarded.32 With this background, consciousness becomes the essential feature of personhood for Locke because it names the point to which past actions, future actions, consequences, rewards, and punishments are plausibly pinned: the consciousness in its continuity over time owns the person’s actions. If someone is conscious of their past actions, it makes sense to reward and punish them because of the continuity in consciousness—»the right and justice of reward and punishment« is founded in identity of consciousness.33 Personhood—and therewith concrete consciousness—is the condition for legal consequences for Locke, as he writes: »[…] to punish Socrates waking for what sleeping Socrates thought, and waking Socrates was never conscious of, would be no more of right than to punish one twin for what his brother-twin did«.34 In Locke’s argument, the forensic image of personal agency is necessitated by a certain notion of justice: namely, retributive justice.

Interestingly, Locke gives the concept of person not only a juridical frame but also a theological one: He uses his idea of consciousness to think about the identity of earthly existence and the resurrected person.35 Based on this, the juridical frame is ultimately a frame of Last Judgment:

»And therefore, conformable to this, the apostle tells us, that at the great day, when every one shall ‘receive according to his doings, the secrets of all hearts shall be laid open’. The sentence shall be justified by the consciousness all persons shall have that they themselves, in what bodies soever they appear, or what substances soever that consciousness adheres to, are the same that committed those actions, and deserve that punishment for them.«36

The juridical and theological framing of this imagination of personhood is important here because I understand them as hints to the concrete practical place of the tradition and effect of this very imaginary: the forensic imagination of personal agency persists paradigmatically in juridical and religious practices. The biblical imaginary entails images that envision and support the forensic image. Neglecting that it does not explicitly talk about individuals but about a potentially collective “you,” the vision of Last Judgment in Matthew 25 could be read as a vision of retributive justice, in which good and evildoers get their merit. This presupposes and perpetuates the image of accountable personhood. The Christian practices of confession, particularly of individual confession, presuppose and perpetuate the forensic image as well. The same holds true for the juridical system in modern societies; it needs to identify persons as accountable and liable entities.

The presuppositions of this and other forensic images of personhood is the individual’s consciousness of one’s actions. To attribute actions to an agent only makes sense if the agent can plausibly be imagined as the conscious author of those actions. Otherwise, reward and punishment were unjust. Locke pins this imagined authorship to consciousness behind the mask that »owns« past and present actions. Hence, what is decisive about the forensic imagination, is the imagined individual’s consciousness behind the mask, the consciousness of one’s actions.

The forensic imagination is highly ambivalent from the perspective of a theological ethic oriented by the goods as freedom, justice, participation, and peace.37 On the one hand, it is emancipative and reconciling because this imagination empowers agency and names concrete responsible agents. On the other hand, the forensic image is problematic in complex societies because most problems have a structural and collective dimension. The tendency to make only one or a few persons responsible for something harmful conceals structural causes and collective contributions and thereby inhibits an improvement of the situation. For example, making individual brokers responsible for the financial crisis of 2008 conceals the contribution of everybody’s greed.

3: Transformations: Digital Cultures

Using the categories of practice and imagination, the ethical reflection of digital transformation will focus on what Felix Stalder has called »the culture of digitality«,38 rather than mere technological possibilities. While much is being written on digital transformation, I want to focus on how the described forensic imagination is present in practices that make »meaningful use« (Reckwitz) of digital technologies. My thesis is this: in digital cultures, power takes forms that undermine the plausibility of the forensic imagination.

This thesis presupposes a differentiation between forms of power and presupposes that images of personal agency persist socially in power-relations. In order to differentiate between forms of power, I draw on the work of both Felix Stalder and Byung-Chul Han who themselves draw partially on Foucault’s theory of power and partially on Max Weber and David Singh Grewal.39 Following them, it makes sense to distinguish at least two forms of power: repressive power on the one hand and constitutive or seductive power on the other.

  • Repressive power: Both, Stalder and Han, mention the repressive Form of the »power of sovereignty«.40 It works through dominance and submission, hierarchies, discipline, orders, commands, rules, and (enforced) obedience.41 It forces people into obeying prohibitions and laws.42

  • Constitutive/seductive power: Drawing on Grewal, Stalder describes the constitutive form of the »power of sociability«.43 It works through quasi-voluntary submission and acceptance of rules: People partake in a network by subtly accepting the rules and protocols that constitute that very network.44 Insofar as »communality« is one of the main features of a culture of digitality (as Stalder claims), the constitutive form of power has gained a new prevalence in digital cultures. Nobody forces me with physical violence to accept the rules of a given social network, but in order to partake in that network I have to accept them quasi voluntarily, independent of my knowledge or consent. Similarly, Han sees a “smart” and “friendly” form of power on the rise.45 According to Han, it is permissive and seductive. This form of power does not work against the individual freedom but through it; submission happens without the individual being conscious of their submission.46 Seductive power seduces freedom into subtle disobedience through possibilities, using our needs and yearnings: It works through the subtle and psychological manipulation of the individual’s decisions.47

From the standpoint of an unconcerned observer, the difference between these forms of power might not seem that decisive.48 In both cases, an entity in power – be it a repressive state or cybernetic system – sets the conditions that influence the agent into a certain behavior.49 Although repressive power works through sanctions while seductive power works through seductions, both forms of power set manipulating conditions that influence individual behavior.

But from the standpoint of the involved participant of social practices, the difference between these forms of power is obvious and decisive: Repressive power needs practices whose participants are informed by the forensic imagination because it needs to identify actors, hold them accountable, and inflict disciplinary action. It needs and produces people who understand themselves as accountable actors, as consciously deciding selves in control of their actions. Repressive power and external means of discipline make it plausible for the individual human to imagine her or himself as a person accountable for the actions she or he has consciously decided to perform because power rewards or punishes the accountable self. It also can make it plausible for individuals to identify the power with accountable persons: Both the one disciplined and the one disciplining can imagine each other as persons, accountable for and conscious of their actions. Accordingly, these practices inscribe the forensic imagination into the social imaginary because such imaginations make practical sense from the perspective of the individual agent.

Insofar as the emerging digital culture entails a shift from the repressive form to constitutive and seductive forms of power, this culture persists in practices that feed on forensic imaginations of personhood while undermining them. This shift makes a relevant difference in the practices of the acting agent. It is in these practices where the seductive forms of power undermine the agent’s forensic imagination, that she or he and the other would »own«50 their actions, insofar as they create »irritating moments« for users and hinder the attribution of power to a responsible person.

How does this happen and what are »irritating moments«? Let’s take the fictional character Fritz as an example: Fritz makes the conscious and accountable decision to become part of a social network in order to stay in touch with friends and colleagues. Because Fritz likes to get “likes” for his posts, he makes the conscious and accountable decision to share certain pieces of information about himself while deliberately refraining from sharing other pieces of information. So far, the forensic imagination makes practical sense to this individual. But behind the scenes, the cybernetic system uses Fritz’s data to personalize what Fritz gets to see: which ads, what movie suggestions, or which search results.51 This can create and has created »irritating moments« for social media users: Fritz gets to see an advertisement on social media that fits his preferences too well – which is irritating – or refers to information he has consciously not revealed at all. Such irritating moments raise questions: Have I revealed more information than I consciously decided to? How self-determined and accountable were the decisions to share information in the first place? Were my actions really my actions? Do social media’s algorithms know me better than I consciously know myself? These question erode the practical plausibility of the forensic imagination of oneself as a consciously deciding and accountable person. From the standpoint of the user, it seems as if the power of the cybernetic systems got behind the mask of conscious personhood. While »irritating moments« erode forensic imaginations on the one hand, they also feed conspiracy theories and apocalyptic narratives such as those summarized by Torsten Meireis:52 »Irritating moments« create plausibility for the narrative that the effects of digital technologies are overwhelming, compelling, mysterious, and uncontrollable.

But the erosion also afflicts the part in power:53 To whom can the seductive power be attributed? Who is accountable for the manipulation or surveillance the individual feels subjected to? The permissive, smart and seductive power described by Han is not visible.54 It has, as Stalder emphasizes, no location but is diffuse and omnipresent.55 This diffusion and anonymity make it impossible to identify it with one responsible person in power. But if no conscious person is accountable, the forensic imagination loses plausibility.

The culture of digitalism also entails practices that make new and extensive uses of the forensic imagination, thereby perpetuating it. For example, Kristy Hess and Lisa Waller have written about the »intensified role of the media in shaming ‘ordinary' people when they commit minor offences« in the digital age.56 The practice of »digital pillory«57 as they call it, rests on the forensic image of personal accountability while perpetuating it.

In view of such problematic roles of forensic imaginations, one might appreciate the practical erosion of the forensic imagination by seductive and permissive forms of power. One can also appreciate how irritating moments reveal how powers work. But without alternative imaginations of personhood, the named erosion might leave one without a sense of human agency at all. Hence the question: How could we imagine personhood in a way that acknowledges those forms of power and their use of freedom working through freedom yet still sustains the person’s sense of agency?

4: Imaginaries II: The Responsorial Imagination of Personhood
(Dietrich Bonhoeffer)

As Locke’s writings already made clear, the forensic imagination of personhood is part of Christian traditions. At least in one simple version, the idea of punishment for evildoers and rewards for the faithful on Judgment Day presupposes and perpetuates the forensic imagination of personhood as conscious agency. Teachings of justification by faith alone as well as confutations of human free will challenge such narratives and their images. This hints towards another way of imaging personhood and human agency in Christian traditions that we can call responsorial imagination of personhood. Bernhard Waldenfels’ work on a »responsive Ethik« implies this type.58 He differentiates between a communicative (or forensic) and a resonpsorial ethic: While the former needs an autonomous self to attribute actions to, the latter works with a self that responds to claims.59 I will interpret some of Dietrich Bonhoeffer’s writings as theological exemplifications of the type »responsorial imagination of personhood« in order to make the point that imaginations of responsorial personhood make better sense in and of practices in digital cultures while sustaining human agency.

Already in his doctoral thesis, Dietrich Bonhoeffer puts a thesis forward on how moral personhood emerges, drawing on I-thou-philosophy. It is the encounter with the Other in which one is a person: When faced with the claim of the Other, experienced as a barrier to one’s own will, one is a person through having to decide.60 For Bonhoeffer, it is the divine »thou« that creates the person in the moment:61

»Der Einzelne wird im ‘Augenblick’ immer wieder Person durch den ‚anderen‘62

Bonhoeffer maintains this basic relational structure up into the fragments of an Ethics, while altering the characterization of the Other. Already, the basic structure of this imagination differs from the forensic one: The forensic imagination pictures a three-figure-relation in which action A is attributed to agent B either by the agent herself or by a (divine) judge C. The responsorial imagination is characterized by a two-figure-relation in which the agent is confronted with the claim of the Other and challenged to respond. Already, this shifts the focus away from the attribution of actions to a person and towards the claims made on the person. This makes every action in question essentially social: The agent is a person in relation63 to others affected by her or his action and is not only a person in the eyes of a disaffected judge or qua having an internal consciousness. This also shifts the focus away from the conditions for attributing actions and personhood towards the claim of the other and the dynamic of the encounter.

In his unfinished Ethics, Bonhoeffer describes the figures in the two-figure-relation of the responsorial imagination differently than in his early writings. With this change, he also deepens the gap with the forensic imagination. In this later work, he uses the term »the responsible« more often than the term »person« for the position of the agent which already mirrors the turn to a responsorial imagination. And—more importantly—he narrates the position of the other not primarily as a »claim« but as the Christ-Reality which encompasses creation, judgment, reconciliation and redemption.64 This change is theologically significant: While the claim would name what Lutherans call »law«,65 the Christ-Reality emphasizes the unity of the word of God as both law and gospel. Bonhoeffer stresses that God reconciled the reality of the world in the Christ-Reality.66 It is this reality to which the life of the Christian should correspond and respond.67 Hence, what humans respond to is not primarily the external and overwhelming reality of God’s claim but the encompassing reality of God’s reconciliation. Moral agency as personhood is not induced by a claim; rather, personhood is created in the encounter with the already reconciled reality. Therewith, the theological standpoint has changed over against the forensic imagination: Personhood evolves not in the contested state of open judgment but as a response to justification.

With this background, the features of the evolving personal agency are decisive. They question the forensic image of a person that consciously »owns and imputes to itself past actions« (see above). As I interpret Bonhoeffer, he imaginatively dispossess the person of their own actions in three ways.

First, he pictures the agent as a responsible person who always acts on behalf of others.68 She or he is not only the conscious I, as for Locke, but »unites in his I the I’s of multiple people«; the »father for example« unities the »I of his family-members […], for whom he is responsible«.69 Hence, the agent’s actions are never only actions on their own behalf, but they are done on the behalf of others.

Secondly, Bonhoeffer pictures the agent as reflecting and acting under conditions of evaluative insecurity: The agent’s consciousness does not own the moral evaluation of his actions. She or he has to be conscious of the potential consequences of the actions. She or he has to weigh advantages and disadvantages and hence acts in the »twilight« of relative decisions, not knowing about their goodness70:

»[D]ie Entscheidung fällt nicht mehr zwischen dem klar erkannten Guten und dem klar erkannten Bösen, sondern sie wird im Glauben gewagt angesichts der Verhüllung des Guten und des Bösen in der konkreten geschichtlichen Situation.«71

Daring to act, faced with the disguise of good and evil, means being dispossessed of, being unconscious of the moral and historic meaning of one’s own actions. Accordingly, the freedom in this imagination is not the freedom of a person that owns, reflects, and consciously controls their own actions, but the »dangerous freedom«72 of a person capable of acting, daring and deciding while not knowing the final quality of one’s actions.

Thirdly, those responsibly dared actions may retrospectively turn out not to have been the person’s actions alone. Thereby, Bonhoeffer opens the notion of acting so that the powers which are active in one’s free action are made obvious. In Bonhoeffer’s account of this, the believing person can come to see those dared actions as God’s actions in history:

»Gerade als der in der Freiheit eigenster Verantwortung Handelnde sieht er sein Handeln einmünden in und fließen aus Gottes Führung. Freie Tat, wie sie Geschichte bestimmt, erkennt sich zuletzt als Gottes Tat, reinste Aktivität als Passivität.«73

This allows for thinking of one’s own actions as retrospectively also somebody else’s action: it disowns the actor of its free action. In Bonhoeffer’s description of responsible action, it is God who is active in the human person’s activity. Formally and fundamentally, this opens the question of which other powers might be active in one’s activity. And it does so while simultaneously acknowledging that the action has been a free daring to act for the agent in the moment in which it was performed.

Therewith, Bonhoeffer imagines the responsible agent as acting not on his own, not by his own agency, and not conscious of the moral quality of his own action. The mask »person« is imagined to be porous. That is, they are permeable to the pending internalized claim of the other »I« and to the action of the other »thou« in one’s own personhood. While this imagination of responsorial agency clearly disowns the agent of their own actions and inscribes the questionability of imputation into the imaginary, it encourages the person to act responsibly on their own and on behalf of others: the imagination is not inhibitory, but conceptualized as empowering. Therefore, the responsorial imagination of personhood provides the horizon in which to imagine oneself and others as acting persons under conditions of digital communication.

5: Proceedings: Imaginations and Praxis

Let me finish by naming three practical proceedings to show that the difference between forensic and responsorial imagination makes a practical difference.

First. People make sense of the cultural reality in which they live. This includes digital technologies. Doing that in the horizon of the forensic imagination of personhood makes it necessary to hold persons accountable. This has the disadvantage of making the imputation of one action to one person an essential art of the imagined personal agency. Under conditions of seductive and constitutive powers in the digital age, the imagination of distinct imputation loses some of its practical plausibility. In the horizon of the responsorial imagination, the response to a given reality is more important than the distinct imputation of any given action. What constitutes responsible personhood according to this image is that one responds to reality by their actions, rather than the clear imputation of actions. The forensic imagination’s necessity to impute is replaced by the constructive question of how to respond. This, of course, can lead to holding those in power accountable but as a matter of responding to a challenging reality and not as an imaginative precondition for moral action as such.

Second. If the distinct imputation of actions loses plausibility due to the work of constitutive and seductive powers, this will undermine the idea of personal agency in the horizon of forensic imaginations: Who am I to make a difference, faced with the global players of the www-world? On the other hand, the responsorial imagination allows for maintaining a sense of agency as both porous and personal under conditions of complexity, insecurity and ambiguity. This imagination expresses a certain habit of understanding oneself as an agent, as having the right to speak and ask questions. The responsorial imagination asks which powers have been operative in one’s free action as free action. It makes that question possible, without letting its answer undermine a sense of personhood and agency. By making those questions posssible and equipping people with the sense of having the right to speak and ask, the responsorial imagination is all but a cover-up for a lack of human agency: In the horizon of this imaginary, it becomes possible to name efficiencies of agency and respond to powers.

Thirdly, the ethical and practical reflection of imaginations makes a difference for educational and ecclesial practices insofar as it makes one favor certain narratives over others. If responsorial imaginations of personhood are taken as ethically advantageous over purely forensic imaginations, narratives will need to be told that transport and envision responsorial imaginations—in class rooms as well as on the pulpit. Most likely, those stories will be less about the impermeable mask of the hero, whose actions change history. More likely, they will be about people who work together, in relation to each other, in solidarity with each other, sympathetic for each, sensitive to the ambivalence of contemporary existence, conscious of the powers that work through one’s own activity and simultaneously not willing to stop working for relative betterment. They will be about the porous masks on stage, which come to be called persons.

Bibliography

Bedford-Strohm, Jonas, Florian Höhne, and Julian Zeyher-Quattlender, eds. (2019) Digitaler Strukturwandel Der Öffentlichkeit: Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven Auf Politische Partizipation Im Wandel. 1. Auflage. Kommunikations- und Medienethik 10. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

Bongaerts, Gregor (2007). “Soziale Praxis Und Verhalten - Überlegungen Zum Practice Turn in Social Theory.” Zeitschrift für Soziologie 36, no. 4 : 246–60.

Bonhoeffer, Dietrich. Werke (DBW) (2015). Edited by Eberhard Bethge et al. 17 vols. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verl.- Haus.

Bourdieu, Pierre (2014). Die feinen Unterschiede: Kritik der gesellschaftlichen Urteilskraft. With the assistance of Bernd Schwibs and Achim Russer. 24. Auflage. Suhrkamp-Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 658. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

Bourdieu, Pierre (2015). Entwurf einer Theorie der Praxis: Auf der ethnologischen Grundlage der kabylischen Gesellschaft. 4. Aufl. Suhrkamp-Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 291. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

Buber, Martin (2017). “Ich und Du [1923].” In Das dialogische Prinzip. Edited by Martin Buber. 14. Aufl., 9–135. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verl.- Haus.

Castoriadis, Cornelius (1990 [1984]). Gesellschaft Als Imaginäre Institution: Entwurf Einer Politischen Philosophie. Suhrkamp-Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 867. Frankfurt a.M: Suhrkamp Verlag.

Dabrock, Peter (2009). “Wirklichkeit verantworten: Der responsive Ansatz theologischer Ethik bei Dietrich Bonhoeffer.” In Verantwortungsethik als Theologie des Wirklichen. Edited by Wolfgang Nethöfel, 117–58. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

Han, Byung-Chul (2014). Psychopolitik: Neoliberalismus Und Die Neuen Machttechniken. Frankfurt am Main.

Harari, Yuval N (2016). Homo Deus: A Brief History of Tomorrow. Revised edition. London: Vintage.

Hess, Kristy, and Lisa Waller (2014). “The Digital Pillory: Media Shaming of ‘Ordinary’ People for Minor Crimes.” Continuum 28, no. 1: 101–11. doi:10.1080/10304312.2013.854868 .

Hillebrandt, Frank (2014). Soziologische Praxistheorien: Eine Einführung. Soziologische Theorie. Wiesbaden: Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden; Imprint: Springer VS. doi:10.1007/978-3-531-94097-7 .

Höhne, Florian (2014 ). Einer und alle: Personalisierung in den Medien als Herausforderung für eine Öffentliche Theologie der Kirche. Öffentliche Theologie 32. Leipzig: Evang. Verl.-Anst, 2015. Teilw. zugl.: Erlangen-Nürnberg, Univ., Diss., u.d.T.: Personalisierung in den Medien als Herausforderung für eine evangelische Öffentliche Theologie der Kirche.

Höhne, Florian (2019). “Darf Ich Vorstellen: Digitalisierung. Anmekrungen Zu Narrativen Und Imaginationen Digitaler Kulturpraktiken in Theologisch-Ethischer Perspektive.” In Bedford-Strohm; Höhne; Zeyher-Quattlender, Digitaler Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit, 25–46.

Höhne, Florian (2019). “„Öffentlichkeit“ als Imagination und Ensemble sozialer Praktiken. Zur Relevanz einer Schlüsselkategorie Öffentlicher Theologie in digitalen Kontexten.” Ethik und Gesellschaft, no. 1: 1–31. http://www.ethik-und-gesellschaft.de/ojs/index.php/eug/article/view/1-2019-art-1/653.

Kather, Regine (2007). Person: Die Begründung menschlicher Identität. Grundfragen der Philosophie. Darmstadt: Wiss. Buchges.

Lichtenberger, Hans P (2006). “Stellvertretung und Verantwortung bei Dietrich Bonhoeffer und Emmanuel Lévinas.” In Stellvertretung: Theologische, philosophische und kulturelle Aspekte. Edited by J. C. Janowski, Bernd Janowski and Hans P. Lichtenberger, 287–312. Neukirchen-Vluyn.

Locke, John (1924). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Abridged and Edited by A.S. Pringle-Pattison. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Meireis, Torsten (2019). ““O Daß Ich Tausend Zungen Hätte“: Chancen Und Gefahren Der Digitalen Transformation Politischer Öffentlichkeit - Die Perspektive Evangelischer Theologie.” In Bedford-Strohm; Höhne; Zeyher-Quattlender, Digitaler Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit, 47–62.

Müller, Hans-Peter (2014). Pierre Bourdieu: Eine systematische Einführung. 1. Aufl., Orig.-Ausg. Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 2110. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

Pannenberg, Wolfhart (1979). “Person und Subjekt.” In Identität. Edited by Odo Marquard and Karlheinz Stierle. 2., unveränd. Aufl., 407–22. Poetik und Hermeneutik 8. München: Fink.

Pariser, Eli (2012). Filter Bubble: Wie wir im Internet entmündigt werden. München: Hanser.

Quante, Michael (2007). Person. Grundthemen Philosophie. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

Reckwitz, Andreas (2003). “Grundelemente Einer Theorie Sozialer Praktiken: Eine Sozialtheoretische Perspektive.” Zeitschrift für Soziologie 32, no. 4: 282–301.

Rushkoff, Douglas (2011). Program or Be Programmed: Ten Commands for a Digital Age. New York: Soft Skull Press.

Schatzki, Theodore R (2008). Social Practices: A Wittgensteinian Approach to Human Activity and the Social. Digitally printed version, paperback re-issue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Schatzki, Theodore R., Karin Knorr Cetina, and Eike von Savigny, eds (2001). The Practice Turn in Contemporary Theory: [Based on a Conference Held Jan. 4 - 6, 1996 at the University of Bielefeld ]. Transferred to digital printing. London: Routledge.

Schmidt, Jan-Hinrik (2011). Das neue Netz: Merkmale, Praktiken und Folgen des Web 2.0. 2., überarb. Aufl. Kommunikationswissenschaft. Konstanz: UVK, 2011.

Schmidt, Robert (2012). Soziologie der Praktiken: Konzeptionelle Studien und empirische Analysen. Orig.-Ausg., 1. Aufl. Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Wissenschaft 2030. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

Soosten, Joachim von (1992). Die Sozialität der Kirche: Theologie und Theorie der Kirche in Dietrich Bonhoeffers „Sanctorum Communio“. Öffentliche Theologie 2. München: Kaiser. Vollst. zugl.: Heidelberg, Univ., Diss., 1989.

Stalder, Felix (2016). Kultur der Digitalität. Edition Suhrkamp 2679. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

Taylor, Charles (2004). Modern Social Imaginaries. Public planet books. Durham: Duke Univ. Press.

Vogelmann, Frieder (2014). Im Bann der Verantwortung. Frankfurt/New York: Campus Verlag.

Waldenfels, Bernhard (2010). “Responsive Ethik Zwischen Antwort Und Verantwortung.” DZPhil 58, no. 1: 71–81.

Comments
39
Clifford Anderson:

A goal of one strand of AI research (so-called “strong AI”) seems by contrast aimed to cross this divide. But your paper raises the important question of how to judge when an AI crosses the divide, forensically (a la Turing) or perhaps responsorially?

Michael Hemenway:

I LOVE the Buber thought experiment! Would be fascinating to put Buber in conversation with Bruno Latour’s Actor network theory and how human actants relate to other actants in the world.

?
Gotlind Ulshoefer:

I think here it would be helpful to look closely what manipulation means in order to detect the underlying power structures because I was wondering if this kind of “obvious” influence on the behavior or decisions of voters is the same as the structuring of decision-options as e.g. google search results.

Kate Ott:

These are definitely the narratives we need. Do you think the constitution of digital technology leads us there as well and reinforces the responsorial imagination?

Florian Höhne:

Yes, i do: As you argue in your book (“Christian Ethics for a Digital Societey”) digital technologies provide experiences of relationality and being part of a network. That makes it more likely, i would argue, to narrate narratives like that and imagine oneself in that way. Unfortunately, digital technologies also provide the opposite experience, f.e. of being helpless an meaningless faced with an overwhelming network-power.

Kate Ott:

I understand the shift to a responsorial imagination, but I’m not quite sure why this imagination has to act on behalf of others or for the relative better. Is it because of an implicit recognition of relationality and interdependence? Also, my other work on children and ethics has strong resonances with the idea of responsorial imagination that I would like to further explore - https://www.mdpi.com/2077-1444/10/9/525

Kate Ott:

This resonates with what I’m pulling from Gebara. What do you think about a commonality there?

Kate Ott:

Similar to the concept of “they” that I’m trying to play with as a multiplicity in unity.

Kate Ott:

I wonder if this is a bit different than what you describe above. The minor offenses are usually something done offline recorded online and thus the offense isn’t manipulated by the seductive power of digital tech. Maybe I’m missing the definition or examples of the minor offenses? Can you give me an example? Either way, I don’t think the forensic image of personal accountability works (or is fully explanatory) offline or outside of a digital culture as you can tell from my paper ;).

Kate Ott:

Interesting. Are you referring to things like digital triggers (a message notification light) that can cause behavior modification, emotional response, etc?

Kate Ott:

Yes! Is this only in a digital culture or exacerbated in that space?

Florian Höhne:

I would think: not only the digital culture, but i am going to show it for the digital culture

Kate Ott:

I think this is important and would like to see it explored in our conversation.

Florian Höhne:

Yes: I agree, i would like to see the individual-collective accounatbility/sin/action issue explored in our conversation too! :)

Kate Ott:

Interesting that Kant interprets, “secrets of all hearts” to mean an individual punishment per person rather than a judgement on humanity more generally with an accordance based in a calculation that considers the power dynamics of the social imaginary, as though a social action is enacted based in a personal decision-making vacuum.

Florian Höhne:

… yes: and this imagination is even institutionalized in many legal systems as well as vibrant in popular scapegaoting-cultures…

Kate Ott:

How is this racialized, gendered, age-dependent, etc? Are some people more or less “persons” based on how the social imagination weighs personal accountability?

Florian Höhne:

Thank you! Those are very good question. And your excellent paper helps a lot to adress them, i think. Further below, i have tried to situate this imagination at least in a certain class which points to the racial and gender-bias that comes with it as well, maybe. One of my main intention is to show the basic ambivalence of such imaginations: While they are gender and class bound on the one hand, they simultaneously serve as precondition for holding those in power accountable.

Kate Ott:

Another connection to “stories” to discuss throughout the conference.

Florian Höhne:

Indeed! I think there is a lot about narratives and stories, we can talk about and shall discuss. Looking forward to it!

Hanna Reichel:

Hm. If I take your description of the manipulative powers at work above seriously, I would not want to “maintain a sense of agency” - I’d rather call out the lack of it.
To put it differently: Is this new conception of personhood helpful in addressing the ISSUES that emerge from the digital developments, or does it serve to PLACATE?

Florian Höhne:

To my view which is informed in this case particularly by the Praxis-Theory of Bourdieu, one needs a certain habit of understanding oneself as an agent, as having the right to speak and ask questions in order to “call out the lack of it”. If the necessary option faced with certain digital phenomena were protest and fundamental critique (which i am as yet not completely convinced of but not opposed to either), this very critique and protest would need critics and protesters, hence agents who can imagine a reason to protest. Does this make sense?

Florian Höhne:

of course, yes: who. Sorry.

Hanna Reichel:

should this be “who”?

Hanna Reichel:

were they, though? depending on how you define “the digital” it may not have originated with the computer, but with statistics (see Nassehi), and there are other possibilities. I think your and Kate’s point about the notions of personhood also suggests that “the digital” might in some ways have been at work a lot before, say, the internet and social media.

Hanna Reichel:

yeah, ok, I am more with you now

Florian Höhne:

I’, glad to read that: This was also the punch line of the former paragraph…

Hanna Reichel:

So are you suggestiong that we should we see our unconscious, “manipulated” actions (as described above) as God’s activity? That seems highly dangerous

Hanna Reichel:

This to me still seems to be pretty much within a strong notion of conscious decisionmaking - precisely the thing which your account of constitutive and seductive power above debunked as a myth… Do you think Bonhoeffer has traction here?

Hanna Reichel:

Because it seems the development in digital cultures is not just that we aren’t able to fully weigh the consequences of our actions - but that we do things without “deciding” to do them. This, to my mind, seems to be a different problem. Does that make sense?

+ 1 more...
Hanna Reichel:

I really like this idea, but I am as of yet completely unsure how it would track unto digital phenomena. i am curious what you will do with it…

Hanna Reichel:

Does the imagination of oneself as an actor actually have this kind of empowering effect? …

Is your fundamental criticism aimed at the corrosion of the imagination or at the corrosion of the actual freedom of the decision-making? Because, especially in the kind of nudged environment you describe, I might very well be under the impression of making a free choice (whether it’s voting or purchasing or sharing pics) while I have been manipulated into it. My image of myself would not empower me here, it might even prevent me to see the sinister reality. On the other hand, I might be completely capable of making unmanipulated decisions (whatever that might be) without thinking of myself as an autonomous agent…

Hanna Reichel:

I don’t understand how seduction undermines conscious decision. I mean I get why certain environmental nudges etc might make it more difficult to stick to a decision to not share information, but at the end of the day, it doesn’t change the fact that you either decide to share the information or decide not to share the information. The repressive power you described earlier may use force to “nudge” us but that doesn’t take away freedom of choice and decision-making as such, does it? So all I am saying is, I am not sure i see where the exact game-changer lies here. (I have tried to formulate one in my own contribution, because like you I actually do think that we are facing powers that do not track unto our conscious decisions and work independent of them. I don’t think nudging is already it. I’d be curious to hear what you think of it.)

Florian Höhne:

I think it is the personalization of the nudging that bypasses conscious decision-making and changes the game: The nudge appears to my consciousness as part of a socially shared reality (in which everybody is faces with the same nudge and might differently react to it) while it is a reality tailored to my preferences. This personalization and its invisibility is what bypasses consciousness, i would say.

Florian Höhne:

Good point. I have to think about that.

Hanna Reichel:

again, if it is manipulative, this means we are attributing an intended, conscious activity behind it - basically the kind of personhood you claim is eroding in this process. Maybe manipulation is not actually the most helpful category for this? Or is your thesis actually that the concept of sovereign etc. personhood migrates from the individual human agent to… whoever it is now that sits there “manipulating” us. Algorithms? Code? Alexa? Alexa’s developers? etc.

Hanna Reichel:

That sounds very sinister. While I would parse them a little differently, I do generally agree with the shift in the kind of power structures you describe. But maybe the “desire” for an autonomous, conscious subjects re-asserts itself in your own description by ascribing it now to the entity exerting the power? I.e., are we sure that there is a “manipulator” on the other side"? I think the erosion of personhood in terms of conscious decisionmaking and attribution pertains to both “sides” here

Hanna Reichel:

I must say that I see these three different types as not as different as they are often presented to be. All of these are mechanisms of power that are constituted in and through acts of subjectivation. I.e., they produce and rely on a particular type of self-consciousness which is complicit in the exercise of this power over the person.

Florian Höhne:

I agree, that the difference particularly between constitutive and seductive power ist not that huge. Sofar, i thought the difference between repressive and seducitve power were significant because they differ in the mode of subjectivation through which they work. But i am open to changing that opinion .

+ 1 more...
Hanna Reichel:

ha, this is what I discuss as “disciplining surveillance” - I think it has a very strong implicit theology, and the genealogy of its current forms, e.g. in the emergent Chinese Social Credit System, include Bentham’s panopticon and Hieronymus Bosch’s tabletop on the Seven Deadly sins - all of them mediate the disciplining effect through self-consciousness, which — i would argue — is actually not so much a condition as an effect of these processes!

Hanna Reichel:

“object”?

Florian Höhne:

Yes, of course: objekt.

Hanna Reichel:

I think these are very interesting questions indeed, even more as they are very elucidating for what prompts us to treat other HUMANS as persons… In the case of machines, it seems that acts of recognition essentially assign personhood rather than intrinsic qualities. Maybe that is true for humanity as well, in phenomenological as well as theological perspective. I am thinking here of a fascinating chapter in @BeniFriedrich’s dissertation as well…

?
Benedict Schöning:

Following my previous comment I would say, it presupposes a voter who reacts to his environment and the abbility to manipulate this environment.

?
Benedict Schöning:

I guess I follow Stalder 226-228 thinking this different: A cybernetic system does not need to get behind the mask - it treats its objects as black-boxes, stimulates them, measures their reaction and changes the stimuli. Thus it does not treat humans as self-conscious beings. For this system it does not matter (and is not accessible), what exactly is manipulated in the obejct und thus it does not matter if this object is man or machine.

Florian Höhne:

I don’t think your comment is thought differently—it just presupposes a different perspective: I was not talking from the perspective of the manipulating cybernetic system but from the perspective of the manipulated “person”. While the former does not have to get behind the mask the latter still can make the experience that something erosive got behind his or her mask—an experience that makes the imagination less possible to be the actor of one’s own actions.

Florian Höhne:

YES: “It needs the imagination of a consciously deciding self, accoutable for its actions and in control thereof.”

?
Benedict Schöning:

imagination of?

?
Benedict Schöning:

See also Stalder p. 226.

?
Benedict Schöning:

This also reminds me of Reichert, Ramón: Die Macht der Vielen. Über den neuen Kult der digitalen Vernetzung (Edition Medienwissenschaft) Bielefeld, 2013.

Florian Höhne:

Thank you for this reference! :-)

?
Benedict Schöning:

Scapegoating is in this sense not a biblical picture but an idea of its later reception.

Florian Höhne:

Of course, thank you for clarifing this!

+ 1 more...
Frederike van Oorschot:

May I ask you a question on my paper, Florian? What do you think in the light of this description about my attempt, to redefine an authority of Scripture as a procedural and relational recognition? I am looking forward to your comments

Florian Höhne:

I will look into yours.

Frederike van Oorschot:

This reminds me of Kate Otts description of the relation between technology and culture…

Florian Höhne:

Reading her article i found myself very much agreeing to her third notion of technology. So: yes! ;)

Frederike van Oorschot:

I think we should discuss this distinction very carefully, related to all issues of our workshop.

Thank you, Florian!

Kate Ott:

Yes, agreed. This is an important point. I would also like to consider further the role of the technologies and the humans used here that is distinct from the concept of digital participatory cultures as described by Henry Jenkins.

?
Benedict Schöning:

I would replace “surface” with “inter-face” (to add even more complexity). Interfaces are mutually influential: The machine is operated via an anthropomorphic interface, humans act through machine interfaces that become more and more transparent. The “face/person” is thus only accessisble through an interface - as is the machine. There the change happens in digitality.

Frederike van Oorschot:

What I wonder about often in debates on the thing-person bias in digital contexts - and I may ask the question here, too: Does a human-lika practise of conversation, you decribed above, necessarily blurs the distinction between things and persons? Or is it more the irritating/confusing “surface” for the user, we are concerned about?

In orther words: What is changing exactly: the surface accessible to the user oder the distinction between things and persons?

I think, this is of special importance for thinking about imagining oneself and “things” in the digital.

+ 3 more...